// you’re reading...

Featured

Gender and the Philosophy Club

Stephen Stich and Wesley Buckwalter present an experimental philosophy parable

Rubens’s Four Philosophers

Rubens’s Four Philosophers

Once upon a time, a Club was started by some really clever people. It was a very prestigious Club whose members were thought to be some of the deepest thinkers in all the world. Since the members of the Club were lovers of wisdom, they were called “Philosophers”. To get into the Club, one had to be very bright and very well educated; one also had to relish argument and debate and be very good at it. The Club was founded a long, long time ago, back in the days when men got to do all the cool stuff, and women were treated as second-class citizens (or worse!). So there were no women in the Club.

In addition to being very clever, and very good at argument and debate, there was also another requirement for getting into the Club, and that will take a bit of explaining. In their arguments and debates, Philosophers frequently come up with rather odd hypothetical cases – thought experiments, as they are sometimes called – that pose interesting philosophical questions. Some of these thought experiments focus on whether a character in a hypothetical story really has knowledge of some proposition; others ask whether an action recounted in the story was just or morally permissible; still others raise questions about free will, personal identity, meaning and other matters. Here’s an example that focuses on knowledge:

Bob has a friend, Jill, who has driven a Buick for many years. Bob therefore thinks that Jill drives an American car. He is not aware, however, that her Buick has recently been stolen, and he is also not aware that Jill has replaced it with a Pontiac, which is a different kind of American car. Does Bob really know that Jill drives an American car, or does he only believe it?

Thought experiments like this one are called “Gettier cases” since a man named “Gettier” first proposed them. Philosophers often find that they can make spontaneous judgments about these questions. After hearing or reading a thought experiment, a compelling answer just pops into their minds. They have no conscious awareness of the psychological processes that lead to that answer. Nonetheless, the answer seems to be true. Philosophers call these judgments philosophical intuitions.

For some thought experiments, members of the Club found that they had different intuitions. But there were quite a number of philosophical thought experiments about which just about everyone in the Club agreed. Club members took those intuitive answers to be obvious. They very rarely tried to defend those obvious answers, however. Rather, they suggested, the capacity to come up with a correct intuitive answer to a question posed by a philosophical thought experiment was a bit like a perceptual capacity. If I’m looking at a British post box and conditions are more or less normal, it’s obvious that the box is red. I have no conscious awareness of the psychological processes that lead to that judgment, and if I were asked to defend my judgment, I wouldn’t know what to say. There is also another important analogy between intuition and perception. Intuitive judgments, like perceptual judgments, are often taken to be evidence. When Philosophers have the intuition that p, they assume that p (the “content” of the intuition) is likely to be true, and they often go on to use p as a premise in philosophical arguments.

Now to get into the Club, it wasn’t required that one agree with other Philosophers about all the thought experiments on which there was a widely shared consensus. But the more one’s intuitions differed from the consensus, the harder it was to get in. Some Philosophers, back in the old days, had a disparaging term for people whose intuitions differed from the consensus – they were said to have a “tin ear”. People with tin ears had a hard time getting into the Club and they rarely made it into the upper echelons of that rather hierarchical organization.

In the early days, all the members of the Philosophers Club were men. However, many contemporary Philosophers are strongly opposed to gender-based discrimination, and in recent decades they have welcomed qualified women into their Club. While many women were admitted, they remain a surprisingly small minority – to this day men make up almost 80% of the Club. In times gone by, the Psychologists Club, the Biologists Club and lots of other learned clubs were also pretty much restricted to men. But in most of these other clubs, the gender disparity has all but disappeared. In the Philosophers Club, for some reason, it remains stubbornly in place.

About a decade ago, a new line of inquiry emerged in the Philosophers Club, which came to be called “Experimental Philosophy.” Inspired by the work of cultural psychologists like Richard Nisbett, who had shown that there are important cognitive differences in people with different cultural backgrounds, the Experimental Philosophers wondered whether it might be the case that people with different cultural backgrounds had different philosophical intuitions. To find out, they began running experiments. And what they found was pretty interesting.

It turned out that there was actually quite a lot of disagreement in philosophical intuition, and that some of it was correlated with culture. People in some cultural groups tended to have one set of philosophical intuitions, while people in other groups tended to have a different set, though there was plenty of diversity in intuitions among members of each cultural group. These were intriguing findings that came as a surprise to many members of the Club. Moreover, as quickly became evident, they posed a problem for the philosophical practice of using intuitions as evidence. For if different people had different philosophical intuitions – if, for example, someone whose cultural background was Western European had the intuition that in the Gettier case Bob’s belief is not an instance of knowledge, while someone whose cultural background was East Asian had the intuition Bob’s belief is an instance of knowledge, one can’t simply assume that the contents of both intuitions are true. Nor is it obvious how one could determine which group tended to have the right intuitions since, as noted earlier, Philosophers usually don’t argue for or defend their intuitions. Their intuitive judgments are treated as premises, not as conclusions, and, like perceptual judgments, they are usually regarded as more obvious than any argument that might be offered in their defence. The trouble is, what seemed obviously true to most East Asians seemed obviously false to most Westerners. Some Experimental Philosophers went on to argue that in those areas of Philosophy where cultural differences in intuition had been found, Philosophers should no longer rely on the venerable method of using intuitions as evidence. And as time went on, intuitions in more and more areas of Philosophy were shown to be culturally variable.

The reaction to all this among more traditional Philosophers was hardly enthusiastic. And that’s not surprising, since in some parts of Philosophy, intuition-based evidence is just about all the evidence available. Some traditionally minded Philosophers denounced the Experimentalists, saying they “hated” Philosophy. Others asked hostile questions when Experimentalists gave talks, and then tried to shout them down when they answered. But most of those who were unenthusiastic about the Experimentalists’ proposals responded by doing what Philosophers do best: they offered arguments. Some of the arguments focused on the design of the experiments that the Experimentalists had used. Had they, perhaps offered experimental participants too few options? Had they made sure that the participants understood the thought experiment in the way that the experimenters intended? Might different groups of participants be relying on different background assumptions? These were significant challenges, leading the Experimentalists to design better experiments. A productive dialogue ensued, a dialogue that is still very lively.

Some of the critics, however, adopted a much less constructive stance. The Experimentalists, they complained, typically used ordinary people – often students – as experimental subjects. But asking for an ordinary person’s judgments about philosophical thought experiments, they complained, was a bit like asking for the man in the street’s judgments about X-rays. For both X-rays and philosophical thought experiments, they insisted, the judgments that count are the judgments of experts, and in the case of philosophical thought experiments, the experts are the members of the Philosophers Club. Moreover, while ordinary folk might have quite different intuitions about some standard thought experiments, there seemed to be much less disagreement among members of the Club. Indeed, though most members of the Club were from the West, even those few whose cultural background was East Asian usually shared the Club’s consensus.

The Experimentalists were not much impressed by this response. In the case of X-rays, they noted, there are a variety of independent ways of checking on the judgments of experts. If an expert says that a shadow is a cancer, surgery will reveal whether she’s right. But there is no independent check on the accuracy of a philosophical intuition. As for the consensus among members of the Club, well that’s hardly surprising, since people who don’t have consensus intuitions have a hard time getting into the Club.

While all of this was going on, the debate took a new and unexpected turn. And it is at this point, gentle reader, that we, the authors, make an appearance in our own parable. About a year ago, a pair of psychologists began circulating a paper in which they reported that women and men tend to have dramatically different intuitions on some Gettier cases that were similar to those that had played a central role in epistemology over the last 50 years. This led us to wonder whether that was an isolated finding or whether there were more cases in which gender is correlated with philosophical intuition. To find out, we searched the literature, surveyed other Experimental Philosophy researchers, and ran a cluster of new studies using well known philosophical thought experiments that had never been used by researchers interested in gender differences. We found that in many cases, including those that are most commonly used in undergraduate Philosophy textbooks, there are indeed gender differences among college-aged Americans with little exposure to Philosophy. In lots of other cases, no gender differences could be detected. There is no obvious pattern in these findings, and no readily discernable way to predict when gender differences will be found in cases that haven’t yet been studied, and when they won’t. Nor do we know how widespread these gender differences are. Since philosophical intuitions can vary from one culture to another, there is no reason to assume that the gender differences found in college-age Americans will be found among other demographic groups. The only way to find out is to do more experiments. At the time of this writing, the explanation for these gender differences in philosophical intuition is unknown, and we think it would be premature to speculate about what the explanation might be.

We have, however, offered some speculations about the effects of these gender differences. If intuitions are associated with gender, we have suggested, this might help to explain the fact that while the gender gap has disappeared in many other learned clubs, women are still seriously under-represented in the Philosophers Club. Since people who don’t have the intuitions that most Club members share have a harder time getting into the Club, and since the majority of Philosophers are now and always have been men, perhaps the under-representation of women is due, in part, to a selection effect. Of course, this selection effect might be justifiable if the intuitions shared by most Club members were correct. The selection process would then be filtering out people with mistaken intuitions, who might have little aptitude for Philosophy. But as we’ve seen, the traditionalists in Philosophy rarely offer any reason to think their intuitions are correct. They just insist that they are obvious, that most of the other members of the Club agree, and that members of the Club are experts in these things. In light of the evidence uncovered by Experimental Philosophers in recent years, we think these self-congratulatory proclamations of expertise have become something of a scandal.

We have also noted another way in which the use of intuitions as evidence in Philosophy could contribute to the under-representation of women. In her important and widely discussed work, Carol Dweck has found that people differ in how they conceive of intelligence and intellectual abilities. Some people view intellectual abilities as a gift – you either have them or you don’t. Others think that intelligence and intellectual abilities are malleable and that they can be cultivated and expanded with effort and practice. The distinction is important since it is correlated with a surprising range of other traits, particularly in the domain of education. In the current context, the most important of these is that people who view intellectual abilities as a gift tend to get discouraged and lose motivation when they encounter puzzling or confusing material.

People who view intellectual abilities as malleable are significantly less likely to lose motivation in this way. There is also a fair amount of evidence that, among contemporary Americans, men are more likely to view intellectual abilities as malleable, while women are more likely to view them as a gift. Let’s consider how all of this might fit together. Suppose you are a student in a university class in Philosophy and you encounter a philosophical thought experiment that raises a question about whether a character in the story really has knowledge. Your intuitive response is “Yes” and this seems obvious to you. But your professor, like most members of the Philosophers Club, insists that the answer is “No” and that this is obvious. Regardless of your gender, it would not be at all surprising if you found this quite puzzling. But if you are a woman, you would be more likely than your male classmates to conclude that you may not have any talent for Philosophy and to lose your motivation to study it further. The single most well established finding in Experimental Philosophy is that there is plenty of disagreement in philosophical intuitions, particularly among students and others with little philosophical training. So events like the one just described are likely to be a fairly common occurrence. And events like that, we suggest, might play a significant role in generating the egregious under-representation of women in the Philosophers Club.

There is still a great deal to be learned about demographic differences in philosophical intuitions, the processes that generate them, and the reactions people have when they encounter other people – particularly individuals in positions of academic authority – whose intuitions differ from their own. But if the speculations set out in the last two paragraphs are on the right track, then it may well be the case that the venerable practice of relying on intuitions as evidence in Philosophy generates an unintentional bias against women. In addition to a number of other factors, including the explicit bias that some male Philosophers may have against women, the ubiquitous practice of using intuitions as evidence in Philosophy may also be an important part of the explanation of why there are so few women in the Philosophers Club.

Stephen Stich is professor of philosophy at Rutgers University, and Wesley Buckwalter is a PhD student in the department of philosophy at the City University of New York Graduate Center

Subscribe to the magazine and keep up to date with articles as they’re published, and much more

Discussion

15 comments for “Gender and the Philosophy Club”

  1. [...] Stich and Wesley Buckwalter present a slightly irritatingly-written but extremely interesting parable on the relationships between your culture, your gender and your philosophical [...]

    Posted by baalbek.org » Gender, intuition and thought experiments | January 21, 2011, 8:28 am
  2. [...] 7. Culture, gender, and experimental philosophy. [...]

    Posted by Consider Magazine » Blog Archive » Endpoint | January 21, 2011, 11:05 pm
  3. [...] This post was mentioned on Twitter by Melissa Kozma, 0001_xml. 0001_xml said: PhilM- Gender and the Philosophy Club: Stephen Stich and Wesley Buckwalter present an experimental philosophy parable http://bit.ly/fAcSHL [...]

    Posted by Tweets that mention TPM: The Philosophers’ Magazine | Gender and the Philosophy Club -- Topsy.com | January 21, 2011, 11:29 pm
  4. [...] my Honours seminar at UBC is focused on (experimental philosophy generally, no the gender issues) https://philosophypress.co.uk/?p=1751 Just so succinct and well-put, a truth that should not be taken for granted [...]

    Posted by Weekly Links Jan. 21st-28th, 2011 « WhatIBelieveIn | January 28, 2011, 10:55 pm
  5. The terms of the parable don’t seem to account for why there weren’t or aren’t now two ‘clubs’, one for men and the other for women.

    My experience in voluntary email discussion groups is that most participants are male, but no doubt there are other groups that are mostly female.

    Posted by Stephen | March 8, 2011, 3:51 pm
  6. What about the cultural influence on the perception of intelligence as a gift?

    Posted by Ronak M Soni | March 11, 2011, 8:55 pm
  7. What about the scientific influence on the perception of intelligence as a gift - e.g. heritability of IQ?

    Posted by Stephen | March 15, 2011, 1:23 pm
  8. Really terribly written. Phenomenology and hermeneutics have much more interesting things to say about the role of cultural/biological factors in intuition.

    Posted by Erin Plunkett | March 27, 2011, 10:05 pm
  9. As does empirical psychology. It would certainly be interesting to hear more about the origins of divergent ‘intuitions’ from a variety of standpoints, though this might tend to cast doubt on their fitness as the first principles of convincing arguments.

    Posted by Stephen | March 29, 2011, 12:46 pm
  10. Erin wrote “Really terribly written. Phenomenology and hermeneutics have much more interesting things to say about the role of cultural/biological factors in intuition.”

    In the context of the authors’ arguments this assertion strikes me as unintentionally ironic. Asserting one’s intuitions about writing quality and arguments’ interestingness as if they were obvious truths while providing no arguments to substantiate them seems an unintentionally ironic and appropriate addendum to Stich and Buckwalter’s piece.

    Posted by Thomas Wood | March 29, 2011, 2:46 pm
  11. My post was admittedly lazy. To be more specific, I take exception to the authors’ use of the term parable to describe their exercise here. A parable tells us about something using something else, functioning on the same logic as a metaphor or simile. For examples of actual parables, see Kierkegaard’s illustration of the love letter in For Self-Examination or Nietzsche’s story of the madman in Gay Science.
    To call the institution of Philosophy a Club does not a good parable make. The point of comparison here is that both are hard to get into and not always fair in their rules of entry. But is this a truth that anyone has any illusions about? It’s like saying that Florida in summer is a sauna—it’s hot folks!
    A good parable should offer a new way of thinking about something that is already accepted, or it should challenge common wisdom by “making strange” through an unlikely comparison. “Philosophy is a prestigious club” fulfills neither of these functions. And to my mind the cutesy style of the piece (“back in the days where men got to do all the cool stuff,” “it is at this point, gentle reader…”) trivializes the ideas presented, which are actually interesting, though not exactly groundbreaking for anyone who’s read, well, any continental philosophy or social theory from the last 150 years. A good exercise in how cultural milieu affects our sense of the obvious, I guess.

    Posted by Erin Plunkett | April 1, 2011, 10:36 am
  12. what a terrible article. I couldn’t even read it. Were they trying to make it cute? Because it just came across as unnecessarily confusing and patronising.

    Posted by kyleigh | April 11, 2011, 9:20 am
  13. In case anyone wishes to take issue with the content of the article without the cloak of anonymity, here’s what to expect:
    http://www.helmuthnyborg.dk/GlobalWitchHunt/GlobalWitchHunt.pdf
    It seems that the only people to stand up for free speech these days are the far right. To judge from the link, there’s not much of it left in academia.

    Posted by Stephen | May 6, 2011, 11:49 pm
  14. [...] Below is the shortest and most influential article in philosophy, ever. But in addition, here is the brand new controversy over this famous article and correction of our view on knowledge. Be sure to glean as much as you can from this, too: https://philosophypress.co.uk/?p=1751 [...]

    Posted by Readings for Friday, What is knowledge??? « Philosophy 101 | May 19, 2011, 3:50 pm
  15. Re the above, here’s the horse’s mouth:

    Posted by Stephen | June 3, 2011, 8:32 am