// you’re reading...

Essays

In memoriam: the x-phi debate

Tamler Sommers pays his respects

death2001About a year ago I was asked to write an accessible magazine article about experimental philosophy. The piece, as I conceived it, would begin along these (somewhat histrionic) lines:

The controversial new movement called experimental philosophy – “X-phi” as it has come to be known – has generated both excitement and hostility in the philosophical community. Questions abound: Is experimental philosophy the wave of the future or just a passing fad? Can probing for the intuitions of the “folk” tell us anything about philosophical truth? Are philosophers qualified to conduct empirical studies, or should this be left to the psychologists?

And so forth. But I couldn’t do it. I could not get myself to write an essay about the general debate over experimental philosophy. At the time, I had no idea why it was so difficult, but I think I do now. Debates are interesting when there is more than one reasonable position to hold. A debate about whether a particular instance of hate speech should be protected by federal law might be interesting. A debate about the value of freedom of expression laws in general is not. On the question of the general value or viability of experimental philosophy, there is only one reasonable position. This makes it an exceptionally boring debate, and who wants to write about that?

That said, many smart people perceive the disagreement on this issue to be legitimate. Experimental philosophy has received a great deal of attention in scholarly journals and the popular media. Often the topic of these articles is precisely what I claim is a non-issue – the value of experimental philosophy as a movement. And here I am writing about this same topic yet again. But I am not going to provide another argument for an obvious position. Instead, I’m writing this as an obituary – an obituary for the so-called controversy about experimental philosophy, and an attempt to diagnose how it lived as long as it did.

Actually, I might be a little late to the game. The recent installment on experimental philosophy in the New York Times blog forum “Room for Debate” (August 19, 2010) was if not an obituary then a strong signal that the issue was on life support. The blog featured perspectives from six philosophers, both “for” and “against” the new movement. The only problem was that they all seemed to agree about the subject under discussion. The unanimous verdict was that experimental philosophy, as a matter of principle, could offer important insight on deep philosophical problems. Room for debate? There didn’t seem to be any. To the extent that there was disagreement, it concerned the quality of the existing literature. But since no one could discuss specific studies or articles – this was a debate about X-Phi in general, remember – no one could provide a shred of support for their views on that matter. What I learned from the exchange was this: for debates about experimental philosophy to be fruitful and interesting, to be genuine debates, they must be about the details and implications of particular experiments within the literature and not about the potential or in principle importance of the movement as a whole.

For those who are unfamiliar with the only reasonable position about experimental philosophy in general, here it is. Of course, experimental philosophy can make important contributions to philosophical inquiry. I’ll give just two reasons, but there are many more. First, a sizable percentage of philosophical arguments rely on both implicit and explicit appeals to intuitions about cases and principles. Philosophers often assume the reader will have a certain intuition, and they use this intuition as evidence for the truth of key premises in their arguments. They go on to draw substantive philosophical conclusions on the basis of these intuitions. If experimental inquiry reveals that a large portion of reflective people have different intuitions, then the philosopher must either explain away this disagreement or concede that the argument’s application is restricted to the group of people who have the same intuition as the philosopher. This would be a philosophically important concession.

Now as many X-phi opponents will stress, not every philosopher develops arguments that appeal to intuitions – indeed, some are positively suspicious of this practice. It’s not clear that it is even possible to develop substantive intuition-free arguments in some areas (ethics, for example). But suppose that some philosophers are successful in doing so – so what? This would only mean that experimental work on intuitions cannot have a direct impact on those arguments. The work would still have a potential effect on the large majority of philosophical arguments that (often frankly) include such an appeal. No one believes that for a subfield of philosophy to have value, it must bear on every single area and argument in our discipline.

Second, much of the experimental literature aims to examine the origins of our philosophical intuitions and the psychological mechanisms that underlie them. Shedding light on the psychology behind our philosophical beliefs can have important philosophical implications for how we regard these beliefs. Just what these implications are is a matter of legitimate debate (and a fascinating one). Whether there are any implications at all is not. To take just one example, imagine that Nietzsche were correct that conventional Western morality grew out of the resentment of a weak and oppressed people. This would tell us something philosophically interesting about our moral beliefs and attitudes, even if we need sophisticated philosophical analysis to figure out what. And the same reasoning applies to all the core areas of philosophical inquiry. As staunch X-phi “opponent” Timothy Williamson writes in the NY Times blog: “when it comes to philosophical questions about how we gain knowledge from perception, memory and reasoning, it would be crazy to suggest that nothing relevant can be learned from experimental results.”

So if people still wonder whether experimental philosophy can offer insights on deep philosophical questions, you can offer something like the above replies to convince them. (If the person concedes these points but presses you as to whether experimental philosophy is really philosophy, I suggest backing away slowly and avoiding that person in the hallways in the future.) A question remains though: why does the controversy exist in the first place? Why so much hostility directed at experimental philosophy in journals and blogs? Why don’t we find similarly heated debates over the value of metaontology, philosophy of mathematics, and philosophy of law?

Part of the explanation, I believe, involves the mistaken impression that experimental philosophers are secret radicals who want to revolutionize the profession, replacing good old-fashioned philosophical argumentation with surveys, brain scans, and data analysis. Williamson, for example, writes the following in his blog entry:

The real issue concerns the most effective way for each side to learn from the other. There are philosophy-hating philosophers who would like to replace the traditional methodology of philosophy, with their stress on a combination of abstract reasoning and particular examples, by something more like imitation psychology.

Now I am acquainted with dozens of experimental philosophers, including the ones to whom Williamson is likely referring, and they love philosophy as much as anyone diligently cranking out counterexamples to the view of knowledge as justified true belief. It is true, as Williams notes, that some experimental philosophers are on the attack. But their target is not philosophy in general. Rather, it is a particular methodology within philosophy – the use of the philosopher’s own intuitions about cases and principles as evidence for philosophical truth. The experimentalists issue this challenge not because they hate philosophy, but because they believe that the traditional methodology is grounded in empirically implausible assumptions about the universality and stability of the intuitions. It is a philosophical challenge at its core, even if it is motivated by empirical research into the nature of intuitions.

Of course, attacks on the “traditional methodology” existed long before anyone conceived of experimental philosophy as a movement. Nietzsche and Rorty, for example, are two of its sharpest critics. Further, the founding document of the contemporary experimental challenge – Stephen Stich’s 1996 book Deconstructing the Mind – is not itself a piece of experimental philosophy. Rather, the book sets up the following hypothetical: if there is substantial variation about intuitions concerning reference, then serious problems are raised for traditional debates in philosophy of mind (e.g. eliminativism vs. functionalism). What the experimental philosophers have attempted to show is that this variation indeed exists.

It’s also worth noting that this strand within experimental philosophy – what Jonathan Weinberg refers to as “the negative program” – is not the only focus, or even the primary focus, of the movement. Experimental philosophy is a large and diverse field. Many experimentalists accept the dominant methodology for the most part and design their studies to work within that tradition. Most experimental work on free will and moral responsibility, for example, seeks to supplement rather than subvert “armchair” approaches to the topic. And the so-called armchair philosophers in the field tend to embrace their experimentally oriented colleagues. But no one, whatever the focus of their work, seeks to replace philosophy with psychology, imitation or real. As X-phi pioneer and prodigy Joshua Knobe likes to stress, experimental philosophy is not a revolutionary movement; it is a return to tradition, to the naturalistic approach of Aristotle and Hume.

I return to the question then: why has this non-issue generated heated debate and antagonism? Again, I turn to Williamson’s entry at the NY Times blog for clues:

[E]xperimentalists draw lessons for morality from the results of brain scans in comically naive ways, without realizing how many philosophical assumptions they are uncritically relying on in their inferences — precisely because they neglect traditional philosophical skills in making distinctions and assessing arguments. The danger is that the publicity such crude work attracts will give a bad name to constructive developments in which experimental results really do cast light on philosophical questions. (my emphasis)

These remarks, in my view, get to the heart of the problem that X-phi opponents have with the movement. Experimental philosophy, they believe, is attracting far more attention than is warranted by the quality of its output. The issue does not merely concern the perceived lack of rigor in parts of the literature. Every subfield of philosophy including the core areas has examples of crude arguments and sloppy reasoning. But magazines and newspapers tend not to run features on externalist approaches to meaning or the principle of sufficient reason.

On one level, I understand this frustration. I have spent my career working on the free will/moral responsibility problem. Every week, it seems, there is a new article in a popular venue in which a neuroscientist blithely claims to have solved the free will problem in a couple of paragraphs. (Often there’s a snide remark about philosophers thrown into the mix as well). It’s infuriating to all of us who work seriously on the topic. It’s a sad fact of life that some work is good and some work is sloppy, and that the sloppiest work often garners the most public attention. It seems to me, however, that the right way to deal with “crude work” is either to ignore it or to specifically address its flaws. It’s tempting for me and my colleagues (including the experimental philosophers among us) to act dismissively towards entire disciplines because of the simplistic analyses of a few of its practitioners. But we do so at our peril – much insight can be gained from high quality interdisciplinary work on long-standing philosophical problems.

How about the experimental philosophers themselves – are they partly responsible for extending the life of this debate? Perhaps. It is only natural to court controversy when controversy attracts so much attention within and outside the philosophical community. Often, however, experimental philosophers are simply defending their work and approach against the broad-scale attacks of their opponents. But if general sweeping criticism of the movement as a whole is unreasonable, then repeated sweeping defenses are unnecessary – or at least uninteresting. The issue resembles in some ways the controversies over evolution. There are innumerable fascinating debates within evolutionary biology itself, but one quickly grows weary of the general defenses of Darwinism against the attacks of creationists and intelligent design theorists. There is nothing to be gained from such defenses but confirmation of what we already know. In my perfect world, experimental philosophers would restrict their discussions to specific studies and the implications they draw from them – even in venues geared towards wider audiences. And this is largely what is happening, which is why this essay is best regarded as an obituary. The debate over experimental philosophy, if it ever really existed, has reached its fitting end. It is time for philosophers everywhere to move on.

The experimental philosophy debate is survived by articles in the New York Times, The Chronicle of Higher Education, Prospect, Slate, many scholarly journals, and countless blog posts, forums, and podcasts

Tamler Sommers is assistant professor of philosophy at the University of Houston

Subscribe to the magazine to read articles as they’re published and much more

Discussion

13 comments for “In memoriam: the x-phi debate”

  1. Perhaps it’s Mill’s influence coming out, but I find advocacy of a metaphilosophical view as ‘the only reasonable position’ mildly less eyebrow-raising if it doesn’t come attached to an injunction to avoid people in hallways if they persist in thinking otherwise.

    Posted by Robert Seddon | March 18, 2011, 1:24 pm
  2. Good point, I forgot about the hallway courtesy principles in On Liberty.

    Posted by Tamler Sommers | March 18, 2011, 7:06 pm
  3. On first coming across the expression “experimental philosophy,” it sounded like an oxymoron. I learned something about what it was through reading about three experiments in which it was used and was bewildered. It appeared those running the experiments had no idea how the things were to be constructed and conducted. My fear was that philosophy out of the desperation to be taken more seriously by the academic community (see above: “Often there’s a snide remark about philosophers thrown into the mix as well”) is grasping at anything it can. Going from the frying pan into the fire came to mind.
    When the author asks “Are philosophers qualified to conduct empirical studies?,” he shows a flawed understanding of what these empirical studies are. Undergraduate students with practically no real knowledge of what they’re doing, with help of an advisor can construct legitimate experiments. So, yes, I think any person with any degree in philosophy can learn to conduct such a study her/himself. There’s nothing very complex or magical about them. Some intelligence has to be used in sampling, wording and administration of questions, and that’s pretty much it. But the results arrived at are almost always questionable. Truths unearthed by such scientific means often deteriorate with time. (See The Truth Wears Off by Jonah Lehrer at: http://www.newyorker.com/reporting/2010/12/13/101213fa_fact_lehrer)
    There are many pitfalls when trying to get information from people through polling. Every student in an introductory psych class is taught that as soon as someone is asked to take part in a poll a transformation takes place in the person. Among other things the person finds it important to appear intelligent, honest, useful, etc. Margaret Mead’s landmark Samoan study about the islander’s attitudes towards sex had great influence on the 1960s sexual revolution. But it appears her results were flawed by the respondents to her question purposely giving her answers they believed she wanted to hear; the answers were not honest.
    A particular difficulty I foresee for X-philo is deciding what a proper sample will be. Probably more than half the population will not understand the language the examiner, I assume, will have to use. I notice the author allows for this by requiring the sample composed of “reflective people.” If X-philo stays the course, I can see hundreds of doctoral theses written just on what that phrase means and how to implement such a sample. Will the truths arrived at in philosophy henceforth be true of reflective people only? Most psych experiments get their samples from their students; it’s natural, and I’m sure the philo experiments will similarly get their samples from their students (what better way to get reflective people?) Of course, you know these are not proper samples.

    Posted by Ralph Sabella | March 20, 2011, 11:13 pm
  4. Although I share the view that it is more fruitful to discuss a particular issue, than some general notion on the nature of philosophy I cannot resist to comment.

    A tacit assumption in x-phi seems to be that philosophical arguments cannot be free from appeals to some sort of intuition. One would assume that, in order for x-phi to be an interesting project, it should be required that we really cannot free ourselves from these commitments to intuition in our arguments. Otherwise one could weed out dubious commitments from ones arguments and stick with arguments that are pure. No questionnaires or experiments needed.

    Now this seems somewhat paradoxically to be a very rationalistic notion. Mysterious intuitions have to play a very prominent role in philosophy for x-phi to be really interesting.

    Moreover it seems that the role of x-phi can easily be taken to be largely negative (or non constructive). It shows that appeals to intuitions might be unwarranted in some sense. There seems to be at least two explanations for such a failure. Either we are not petitioning a true intuition (whatever that would be) or that intuitions cannot generally be trusted and that arguments based on them are faulty.

    The first alternative is reminiscent of some forms of old fashioned rationalism(,as already noted).

    While the second can be taken to imply either of two things. Firstly one could understand it as meaning that that philosophical arguments are in general faulty, because they make necessarily appeals to intuitions which are not universal. Which is a rather bleak view of philosophical argumentation.

    The other ones is of course that intuitions can be eliminated from an argument altogether without destroying it, which makes x-phi somewhat uninteresting, because then we should just avoid making appeals to intuition.

    ——————

    Another different point is that one could in the same spirit argue that that the philosopher is never free from appeals empirical facts and that philosopher should go around examining these empirical claims.

    But this is already done by science.

    Posted by CVP | March 21, 2011, 6:33 pm
  5. To CVP:
    I like your paradox.
    I too wondered about the necessity of intuitions in philosophical arguments. I was going to include in my comment above, that philosophers need only be circumspect in their uses of intuitions, or not use them at all, and they would be able to go on their merry way as before. The use of intuitions in arguments seemed an insubstantial reason to hang a whole new subfield on, but not being a philosopher and seeing all these smart people excited over the issue I cowered into temporary submission and decided to limit myself to the problem of sampling.

    Posted by Ralph Sabella | March 21, 2011, 10:36 pm
  6. Hi Ralph,

    I agree with much of what you’re saying–but also think it’s a classic case where it’s more fruitful to discuss specific studies rather than X-Phi as a whole. For example, you write: “Probably more than half the population will not understand the language the examiner, I assume, will have to use.”

    That might (probably is) true of certain studies but not others. Knobe’s classic “help/harm” the environment study doesn’t seem to have language that half the people (or anywhere close to that proportion) won’t understand. But other scenarios may not be like that. The only way to either support or challenge that kind of claim is to focus on actual real-life studies.

    CVP,

    You write: “A tacit assumption in x-phi seems to be that philosophical arguments cannot be free from appeals to some sort of intuition.”

    That’s flat-out wrong, and I address that in this essay. There may be a tacit assumption that SOME philosophical argument rely on appeals to intuition. But that assumption is obviously true. To give just one clear example, Susan Wolf’s defense of the sane deep self view relies on our intuition that Jojo, the son of a dictator, is not responsible for his actions because of his upbringing.

    That said, in some areas, perhaps ethics especially, it really doesn’t seem possible to construct arguments without appeals to intuition. If some form of reflective equilibrium is your methodology, you rely on starting intuitions about principles and cases. And it clearly (often explicitly) is the methodology that many ethicists use. But again, X-Phi need not assume anything about the possibility of not appealing to intuition. As long as there are actual arguments out there that do this, then it’s prima facie interesting to question whether we have the intuitions that philosophers say we have…

    Posted by Tamler Sommers | March 22, 2011, 8:13 pm
  7. Tamler writes:

    “You write: “A tacit assumption in x-phi seems to be that philosophical arguments cannot be free from appeals to some sort of intuition.”

    That’s flat-out wrong, and I address that in this essay. There may be a tacit assumption that SOME philosophical argument rely on appeals to intuition.”

    The keyword here is seems. I did not mean that you must give intuitions a prominent role (see later part of the comment).

    The point here is that the importance of x-phi seems is to be directly proportional to the weight given to intuitions in philosophical arguments.

    Posted by CVP | March 24, 2011, 8:00 am
  8. CVP, you write:

    “The keyword here is seems. I did not mean that you must give intuitions a prominent role (see later part of the comment).”

    No, but you seemed to mean that X-phi assumes that phil. arguments cannot be free of appeals to intuition. But X-phi doesn’t assume this, nor does it need to.

    “The point here is that the importance of x-phi seems is to be directly proportional to the weight given to intuitions in philosophical arguments.”

    Again, it doesn’t have to be all or nothing. It could be that many (but not all) philosophical arguments appeal to intuition. Experimental work can be relevant to those arguments. I think we agree on that, right? So if we disagree at all (and I’m not sure we do), it’s on the question of how extensive the appeal to intuition is in philosophy. Would you agree that the vast majority of arguments in ethics do contain such appeals, and often explicitly so?

    Posted by Tamler Sommers | March 24, 2011, 11:05 pm
  9. Tammler:

    Yes we agree on that such studies has some value.

    But you write:

    “So if we disagree at all (and I’m not sure we do), it’s on the question of how extensive the appeal to intuition is in philosophy.”

    I do not think it is only a matter of degree or in other words a matter of what importance is given to intuitions in philosophy.

    This is because if one gives them some importance, then one should be able to explain what intuitions are and what there role is. And this seems to create a tension between x-phis empirical method and the mystical notion of intuition.

    Another alternative is of course to regard intuitions as completely useless, but this makes x-phi uninteresting, since intuitions are useless from the outset.

    A more particular form of this would be to regard intuitions as ultimately grounded in experience. This would make x-phi an empiricist project. Is it?

    You write:

    “Would you agree that the vast majority of arguments in ethics do contain such appeals, and often explicitly so?”

    Yes I think this is true in some vague manner.

    Posted by CVP | March 25, 2011, 6:15 pm
  10. I’m worried that this obituary of the debate about the significance of X-Phi has been written too soon. There are several interesting positions to be held with respect to the question and not all of them agree with you. One of them is outlined in Antti Kauppinen’s ‘The Rise and Fall of Experimental Philosophy’ paper (Philosophical Explorations 2007 - available here: http://www.unc.edu/~knobe/kauppinen.pdf).

    Now, it is true that in the same issue there are clever responses by Knobe and Nadelhoffer and Nahmias. But, it is not clear to me that the X-Phiers win this match. As far as I have seen, no knock-down arguments have been given to Kauppinen’s objections.

    Of course, the proof in the end will be in the pudding. Personally, I find it too early to call whether X-Phi will be able to make significant, lasting contributions to key deep philosophical problems. It will be wonderful it can, but I’m yet to be convinced.

    Posted by Jussi Suikkanen | March 27, 2011, 1:55 pm
  11. Jussi,

    If it’s too early to call whether X-Phi will make significant contributions, then why is it a matter of philosophical interest to speculate on that question? I don’t get it. It’s also too early to call whether debates in metaontology will make significant contributions, but I wouldn’t write articles about the rise and fall of metaontology….

    Posted by Tamler Sommers | March 29, 2011, 10:59 pm
  12. Sorry. I don’t get the question. I don’t think anyone has claimed that it is a matter of philosophical interest to speculate whether it is too early to call whether X-Phi will make significant contributions. I do recommend reading Antti’s paper. It argues very plausible that there some theoretical reasons why the whole project of X-phi might face methodological problems which will be very hard to overcome. Some of the defenders of that movement have claimed that they will be able to do so by improving their methodology. I’m yet to be convinced that they will be able to do so. I think the burden is on the experimentalists here. But, yeah, please do read the paper.

    Posted by Jussi Suikkanen | March 30, 2011, 9:55 pm
  13. I’ve read Antti’s paper, Jussi. It was one of the pieces that motivated me to write this article in the first place. I agree that he’s identified some methodological difficulties–if that were the point of the paper, fine. I would applaud it. But that’s not the point of “The rise and fall of experimental philosophy.” Like so many critics of X-Phi, the move from ‘this is a problem with these studies’ to ‘this is a fundamental problem with X-phi in general’ is too quick and unmotivated. You don’t find parallels in other areas of philosophy.

    Posted by Tamler Sommers | March 31, 2011, 11:13 pm